Essays on Knowledge. How Knowledge is Perceived Development Importance of Education Knowledge 2 Pages. The amount of people that understand the importance of knowledge in today’s world and Socrates world are very different. The Apology is a book written by the philosopher, Plato, that describes why knowledge is important The essays cover difficult topics, but they are rewarding, as one would expect from high quality works on a topic probing the intersection of knowledge, language, mind, and action. The book opens with a long (52 pages) state-of-the-debate essay written by the editors, John Bengson and Marc A. Moffett Feb 23, · Essay. November 5, by essaybanyan. “Learning gives creativity, Creativity leads to thinking, Thinking provides knowledge, and Knowledge makes you great”. These lines had been said by our former president and great scientist Dr. A.P.J. Abdul Kalam focusing on the importance of knowledge. It is the power of knowledge which made
Long and Short Essay on Knowledge in English for Children and Students
The growing and well-deserved interest in the nature and grounds of knowledge-how in recent years is crowned with this excellent collection of original essays from some of the most able philosophers working in the field.
The collection is balanced in two respects: it contains essays defending opposing accounts on knowledge-how, and it also contains essays that are devoted to delineating the broad implications and applications of taking a particular stand on the topic.
All essays in the book are written with admirable clarity, awaken a desire to ponder the ongoing debates, and are rich in examples, essays on knowledge.
The essays cover difficult topics, essays on knowledge, but they are rewarding, as one would expect from high quality works on a topic probing the intersection of knowledge, language, mind, and action. The book opens with a long 52 pages state-of-the-debate essay written by the editors, John Bengson and Marc A, essays on knowledge.
The length of the essay is consistent with, and justified by, essays on knowledge, its primary goal of providing an exhaustive outline of the central philosophical positions and questions about knowledge-how. Bengson and Moffett aim, among other goals, to make explicit the core contentions essays on knowledge the opposing views aptly named 'intellectualism' and 'anti-intellectualism' after Ryle's and They also identify specific instances of these generic views, rehearse the now-standard arguments for and against, and gesture at the echoes that a philosophical theory of intelligence may generate in converging areas of inquiry.
The rest of the book is divided into four parts. Part I, "Ryle's Legacy," consists of two chapters -- one by Paul Snowdon and one by Jennifer Hornsby -- that evaluate Ryle's attack on intellectualism and his alternative conception of knowledge-how. Part II, "Philosophical Considerations," includes five chapters. Three of these chapters by Yuri Cath, Berit Brogaard, and Bengson and Moffett focus on the question whether knowledge-how is a species or kind of knowledge-that.
The remaining two attempt to identify some issues that recent discussions of knowledge-how have ignored or overlooked: Julie Annas distinguishes between two kinds of knowledge-how, and Alva Noë discusses a "third realm" that lies between the entirely subjective realm of mere taste and the entirely objective realm of the rule-governed.
Part III, essays on knowledge, "Linguistic Perspectives," brings together three essays, by Jonathan Ginzburg, David Braun, and Laura A, essays on knowledge. Michaelis, on the syntax and semantics of knowledge-how constructions and their relevance to the debate between intellectualism and anti-intellectualism. Part IV, "Implications and Applications," includes four chapters, by Katherine Hawley, Michael Tye, Michael Devitt, and Ian Rumfitt, discussing the significance of philosophical work on knowledge-how for ethics, essays on knowledge, philosophy of mind, philosophy of language, and philosophy of logic.
There is no essay in this collection that does not deserve wide notice and sustained study. Unfortunately, in a review of this length it is impossible to discuss all the essays with the depth of thought they themselves exhibit. In what follows I will examine some of the issues that I find especially interesting. Let me start with what Snowdon calls "the central mystery of Ryle's approach" The mystery is how to account for "the relation between the debate about intellectualism and the debate about the nature of know how" Ryle's "Knowing How and Knowing That" opens with a preamble in which a doctrine he subsequently calls 'intellectualism' is characterized as the view that "intelligence concepts" such as "clever," "wise," "prudent," "sensible," and "skillful" are applied to practical actions in virtue of being accompanied by "internal acts of considering propositions" Ryle1.
Why is this? How does Ryle's attack on intellectualism sit with what he has to say about the relation between knowing how and knowing that? This is not in fact much of a mystery if mysteries are supposed to be extremely resistant to a solution or dissolution.
What we have here is more like a puzzle crying for a substantial interpretation. Snowdon himself gives a brief sketch of a solution to the puzzle 67and Bengson and Moffett provide a more detailed interpretation of how to understand essays on knowledge Ryle sees the bearing of his rejection of intellectualism on his thesis that knowing how cannot be defined in terms of knowing that The answer these three philosophers give to this question is basically that intellectualism is a general thesis about mind and action, a thesis which can be tested by evaluating one of its instances -- i.
On this approach, intelligence has many varieties, of which knowledge-how is merely an instance. If this is so, then if knowledge-how cannot be accounted for solely in terms of knowledge-that, then intellectualism fails. An alternative approach to the puzzle would be to take Ryle as holding that having intelligence is having knowledge-how and also that intelligence concepts like "clever," "wise," and "acute," are disguised adverbs that qualify the object of knowledge-how in question.
Some evidence for these two claims can be found, respectively, in the following passages:. Essays on knowledge a person knows how to do things of a certain sort, we call him 'acute', 'shrewd', 'scrupulous' Ryle Intelligently to do something, essays on knowledge. is not to do two things, one "in our heads" and the other perhaps in the outside world; it is to do one thing in a certain manner.
It is somewhat like dancing gracefully Ryle3. On this approach, "Michael is a wise chess player" can be read as expressing, roughly, essays on knowledge, that Michael knows how to play chess wisely, and "Michael is now wisely playing chess" can be read as expressing, roughly, essays on knowledge, that Mike's knowing how to play chess wisely is now actualized, given that on Ryle's view, knowledge-how is a disposition that may be actualized I do not mean to suggest that this is the correct interpretation of how Ryle construes the relation between intelligence and knowledge-how, but only that this is one essays on knowledge interpretation, essays on knowledge.
Unfortunately, however, neither interpretation sits well with Ryle's main argument against intellectualism, namely, the famous regress argument. The problem is that the regress argument loses its spell when applied against the thesis that knowledge-how can be accounted for solely in terms of knowledge-that.
Let me explain. Ryle's regress argument starts with asking the question what makes the supposedly intelligence-conferring "internal act of considering propositions" themselves intelligently performed. It seems that such an act must itself be intelligently performed because otherwise it does not appear to be capable of conferring intelligence to any practical action. However, if it essays on knowledge intelligently performed, then it appears that, according to intellectualism, there must be another internal act of considering a proposition which confers intelligence to the initial act in question.
Since the same reasoning applies to this further internal act, a regress ensues. Now suppose that what makes a practical action an exercise of knowledge-how and what therefore makes it intelligent is a piece of knowledge-that. If we attempt to apply the regress argument against this supposition, then we need to argue that the piece essays on knowledge knowledge-that in question must itself be "intelligently performed", which may possibly mean, for all I can see, that the belief which is a part of that piece of knowledge is justified, essays on knowledge.
Now, of course, essays on knowledge, there is a good old epistemic regress problem with respect to the justification of our beliefs. But this is not a special problem for the intellectualist but a general problem for all philosophers of knowledge.
If Ryle's regress argument against intellectualism reduces to a general epistemic regress problem when applied to the intellectualist-looking thesis that knowledge-how is to be accounted for solely in terms of knowledge-that, then it does not have any special force against that thesis. However, Ryle's regress argument is designed to have such a special force against intellectualism.
So, essays on knowledge, what is thought to count against intellectualism cannot, by itself, be supposed to count against the thesis in question. This implies that the relation between intellectualism and the alleged intellectualist-looking thesis is harder to specify than what the above interpretations suggest. So, the puzzle appears to remain unsolved. Let me now turn to a related topic, the question whether knowledge-how is a species of knowledge-that.
Jason Stanley and Timothy Willamson made a strong case for the thesis that knowledge-how is "simply a species of propositional knowledge" Cath, in his essay in this collection, provides some persuasive reasons against this thesis.
He argues that knowledge-that is typically or standardly taken to be subject to some conditions which knowledge-how need not satisfy, such as the anti-luck condition, the undefeated justification condition, and the belief condition. So, there are cases where knowledge-how and knowledge-that come apart. To get a sense of Cath's arguments, consider his "Lucky Light Bulb" case. Charlie wants to learn how to change a light bulb and consults a copy of The Idiot's Guide to Everyday Jobs.
However, unbeknownst to Charlie, all the copies of the book except his are filled with misleading instructions, and Charlie is extremely lucky to have the accurate one. Charlie reads his copy and grasps the instructions therein perfectly. So, essays on knowledge, there is a way, call it 'w 1 ', such that Charlie now believes that w 1 is a way for him to change a light bulb. Intuitively, Charlie now knows how to change a light bulb but he does not know that w 1 is a way for him to change the light bulb.
This is because Charlie's belief is only accidentally true: Charlie could have easily bought a copy filled with misleading instructions and thus have easily come to believe something false about ways of changing a light bulb, essays on knowledge.
However, Charlie's being epistemically lucky with respect to the truth of his belief about w 1 does not seem to be a reason to think he thereby fails to possess the corresponding knowledge-how. This is a beautiful and strong argument.
I am inclined to think that it essays on knowledge what it is intended to show: that knowledge-how is not subject to some constraints that are traditionally associated with knowledge-that. If that is so, then it seems that there are two options for the intellectualist: either to argue that there is a kind of knowledge-that that is not subject to the traditional constraints mentioned above and that knowledge-how is a species of this non-traditional kind of knowledge-that, or to maintain that traditional constraints hold for all cases of knowledge-that and to retreat to a somewhat weaker intellectualist thesis that knowledge-how is a matter of standing essays on knowledge an intentional relation to a proposition other than the knowledge-that relation.
Cath provides a sketch for the latter, while Brogaard argues for the former in her contribution to the volume. Unfortunately for the intellectualist, neither option appears to be promising. Let me first say a couple of things about Cath's suggestion, and then I will turn to Brogaard's account. S knows how to Φ if, and only if, there is some way w to Φ such that:. a S stands in the seeming relation to the proposition that w is a way to Φ, and.
b S entertains the proposition that way w is a way to Φ under a practical mode of presentation The notion of "a practical mode of presentation" is adapted from Stanley and Willamson's proposal on knowledge-how, and let us not worry about what it is. The "seeming" relation in question is, Cath takes it, different from believing. Let us also not worry whether there is indeed such a propositional attitude that is considerably weaker than believing.
What is striking about Cath's proposal is that nothing on the right-hand side of the biconditional appears to be capable of essays on knowledge for, or amounting to, knowledge. If knowledge-how is a form of knowledge, and if no form of knowledge can be accounted for by the relations of seeming which is weaker than believing and entertaining under a practical mode of presentation, then Cath's proposal appears to be inadequate.
The problem is not merely that, on Cath's proposal, essays on knowledge, there is no mention of traditional conditions for knowledge such as justification and belief.
After all, Cath's primary aim in his essays on knowledge is to show that those conditions need not be satisfied by knowledge-how. The problem is that what is offered in place of those constraints does not even come close to being able to provide a plausible analysis of any form of knowledge, let alone, in our case, of knowledge-how.
Cath's proposal is perhaps, as Brogaard suggests, that 'know' "ambiguously denot[es] sometimes a knowledge state and sometimes an intellectual seeming state" essays on knowledge If this is the correct reading of Cath's proposal, then it is also not without problems. First, I do not think there are any convincing reasons to think that when 'know' is followed by 'that' and 'how', it turns out to have different meanings, namely, knowing and seeming, respectively.
Notice that there are knowledge- wh constructions such as 'know why', 'know where', and 'know when', as well as constructions like 'know that' and 'know how'. Are we to say, following Cath's proposal, that 'know' denotes different states in these constructions? Second, if 'knowledge-how' were to denote seeming under a practical mode of presentationthen it would be impossible to have seeming without knowledge-how.
But it appears that there are such cases. Consider Susan, who is an anxious driver who gets overexcited and loses control whenever she tries to parallel park her car. It is the same story each time: her car is tired of the accidents Susan has every time she tries to parallel park it. This is so despite the fact that Susan took every theoretical and practical lesson from the best drivers available in the country. Now, there appears to be some way w to essays on knowledge park Susan's car such that Susan stands in the seeming relation under a practical mode of presentation to the proposition that w is a way to parallel park her car, essays on knowledge.
Yet, intuitively, Susan does not know how to parallel park her essays on knowledge as the numerous accidents she has had bear witness. If that is so, then knowledge-how and seeming under a practical mode of presentation may come apart, which implies that knowledge-how is not seeming.
Let me now turn to Brogaard's account of knowledge-how, which offers a radical reconceptualization of knowledge-that, essays on knowledge. Brogaard argues that there are primitive knowledge- that states that are not belief entailing and also that some knowledge-how states are primitive non-belief entailing knowledge-that states:.
10 Lines on Knowledge is Power Essay - Essay Writing
, time: 4:24≡Essays on Knowledge. Free Examples of Research Paper Topics, Titles GradesFixer
+ Words Essay on Knowledge is Power. Knowledge Is Power Essay- Knowledge is something that will serve you your whole life. The most powerful thing in the world is knowledge because it can create and destroy life on earth. Moreover, knowledge helps us distinguish between humans and animals. Knowledge is the ability to use your knowledge to Estimated Reading Time: 3 mins Aug 08, · Short Essay on Knowledge – Essay 1 ( words) Knowledge is awareness and understanding of something such as information, facts, narration or skills gained through education and experience by observing, discovering or learning. It refers to both theoretical and practical comprehension of a subject. Knowledge comes into practice with our blogger.comted Reading Time: 9 mins May 17, · Long Essay on Knowledge is Power in English words. This extended essay is suitable for students studying in classes 6,7,8, 9, and 10, respectively. This essay is written to assist and guide success to those aspiring students applying for competitive examinations. Knowledge is a broad concept with no possible blogger.comted Reading Time: 6 mins
No comments:
Post a Comment